Against Eunomius.

 Contents of Book I.

 Contents of Book II.

 Contents of Book III.

 Contents of Book IV.

 Contents of Book V.

 Contents of Book VI.

 Contents of Book VII.

 Contents of Book VIII.

 Contents of Book IX.

 Contents of Book X.

 Contents of Book XI.

 Contents of Book XII.

 §1. Preface.—It is useless to attempt to benefit those who will not accept help.

 §2. We have been justly provoked to make this Answer, being stung by Eunomius’ accusations of our brother.

 §3. We see nothing remarkable in logical force in the treatise of Eunomius, and so embark on our Answer with a just confidence.

 §4. Eunomius displays much folly and fine writing, but very little seriousness about vital points.

 §5. His peculiar caricature of the bishops, Eustathius of Armenia and Basil of Galatia, is not well drawn.

 §6. A notice of Aetius, Eunomius’ master in heresy, and of Eunomius himself, describing the origin and avocations of each.

 §7. Eunomius himself proves that the confession of faith which He made was not impeached.

 §8. Facts show that the terms of abuse which he has employed against Basil are more suitable for himself.

 §9. In charging Basil with not defending his faith at the time of the ‘Trials,’ he lays himself open to the same charge.

 §10. All his insulting epithets are shewn by facts to be false.

 §11. The sophistry which he employs to prove our acknowledgment that he had been tried, and that the confession of his faith had not been unimpeached,

 §12. His charge of cowardice is baseless: for Basil displayed the highest courage before the Emperor and his Lord-Lieutenants.

 §13. Résumé of his dogmatic teaching. Objections to it in detail.

 §14. He did wrong, when mentioning the Doctrines of Salvation, in adopting terms of his own choosing instead of the traditional terms Father, Son, and

 §15. He does wrong in making the being of the Father alone proper and supreme, implying by his omission of the Son and the Spirit that theirs is impro

 §16. Examination of the meaning of ‘subjection:’ in that he says that the nature of the Holy Spirit is subject to that of the Father and the Son. It i

 §17. Discussion as to the exact nature of the ‘energies’ which, this man declares, ‘follow’ the being of the Father and of the Son.

 §18. He has no reason for distinguishing a plurality of beings in the Trinity. He offers no demonstration that it is so.

 §19. His acknowledgment that the Divine Being is ‘single’ is only verbal.

 §20. He does wrong in assuming, to account for the existence of the Only-Begotten, an ‘energy’ that produced Christ’s Person.

 §21. The blasphemy of these heretics is worse than the Jewish unbelief.

 §22. He has no right to assert a greater and less in the Divine being. A systematic statement of the teaching of the Church.

 §23. These doctrines of our Faith witnessed to and confirmed by Scripture passages .

 §24. His elaborate account of degrees and differences in ‘works’ and ‘energies’ within the Trinity is absurd .

 §25. He who asserts that the Father is ‘prior’ to the Son with any thought of an interval must perforce allow that even the Father is not without begi

 §26. It will not do to apply this conception, as drawn out above, of the Father and Son to the Creation, as they insist on doing: but we must contempl

 §27. He falsely imagines that the same energies produce the same works, and that variation in the works indicates variation in the energies.

 §28. He falsely imagines that we can have an unalterable series of harmonious natures existing side by side.

 §29. He vainly thinks that the doubt about the energies is to be solved by the beings, and reversely.

 §30. There is no Word of God that commands such investigations: the uselessness of the philosophy which makes them is thereby proved.

 §31. The observations made by watching Providence are sufficient to give us the knowledge of sameness of Being.

 §32. His dictum that ‘the manner of the likeness must follow the manner of the generation’ is unintelligible.

 §33. He declares falsely that ‘the manner of the generation is to be known from the intrinsic worth of the generator’.

 §34. The Passage where he attacks the ‘ Ομοούσιον , and the contention in answer to it.

 §35. Proof that the Anomœan teaching tends to Manichæism.

 §36. A passing repetition of the teaching of the Church.

 §37. Defence of S. Basil’s statement, attacked by Eunomius, that the terms ‘Father’ and ‘The Ungenerate’ can have the same meaning .

 §38. Several ways of controverting his quibbling syllogisms .

 §39. Answer to the question he is always asking, “Can He who is be begotten?”

 §40. His unsuccessful attempt to be consistent with his own statements after Basil has confuted him.

 §41. The thing that follows is not the same as the thing that it follows.

 §42. Explanation of ‘Ungenerate,’ and a ‘study’ of Eternity.

 Book II

 Book II.

 §2. Gregory then makes an explanation at length touching the eternal Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit.

 §3. Gregory proceeds to discuss the relative force of the unnameable name of the Holy Trinity and the mutual relation of the Persons, and moreover the

 §4. He next skilfully confutes the partial, empty and blasphemous statement of Eunomius on the subject of the absolutely existent.

 §5. He next marvellously overthrows the unintelligible statements of Eunomius which assert that the essence of the Father is not separated or divided,

 §6. He then shows the unity of the Son with the Father and Eunomius’ lack of understanding and knowledge in the Scriptures.

 §7. Gregory further shows that the Only-Begotten being begotten not only of the Father, but also impassibly of the Virgin by the Holy Ghost, does not

 §8. He further very appositely expounds the meaning of the term “Only-Begotten,” and of the term “First born,” four times used by the Apostle.

 §9. Gregory again discusses the generation of the Only-Begotten, and other different modes of generation, material and immaterial, and nobly demonstra

 §10. He explains the phrase “The Lord created Me,” and the argument about the origination of the Son, the deceptive character of Eunomius’ reasoning,

 §11. After expounding the high estate of the Almighty, the Eternity of the Son, and the phrase “being made obedient,” he shows the folly of Eunomius i

 §12. He thus proceeds to a magnificent discourse of the interpretation of “Mediator,” “Like,” “Ungenerate,” and “generate,” and of “The likeness and s

 §13. He expounds the passage of the Gospel, “The Father judgeth no man,” and further speaks of the assumption of man with body and soul wrought by the

 §14. He proceeds to discuss the views held by Eunomius, and by the Church, touching the Holy Spirit and to show that the Father, the Son, and the Hol

 §15. Lastly he displays at length the folly of Eunomius, who at times speaks of the Holy Spirit as created, and as the fairest work of the Son, and at

 Book III

 Book III.

 §2. He then once more excellently, appropriately, and clearly examines and expounds the passage, “The Lord Created Me.”

 §3. He then shows, from the instance of Adam and Abel, and other examples, the absence of alienation of essence in the case of the “generate” and “ung

 §4. He thus shows the oneness of the Eternal Son with the Father the identity of essence and the community of nature (wherein is a natural inquiry int

 §5. He discusses the incomprehensibility of the Divine essence, and the saying to the woman of Samaria, “Ye worship ye know not what.”

 §6. Thereafter he expounds the appellation of “Son,” and of “product of generation,” and very many varieties of “sons,” of God, of men, of rams, of pe

 §7. Then he ends the book with an exposition of the Divine and Human names of the Only-Begotten, and a discussion of the terms “generate” and “ungener

 Book IV

 Book IV.

 §2. He convicts Eunomius of having used of the Only-begotten terms applicable to the existence of the earth, and thus shows that his intention is to p

 §3. He then again admirably discusses the term πρωτότοκος as it is four times employed by the Apostle.

 §4. He proceeds again to discuss the impassibility of the Lord’s generation and the folly of Eunomius, who says that the generated essence involves t

 §5. He again shows Eunomius, constrained by truth, in the character of an advocate of the orthodox doctrine, confessing as most proper and primary, no

 §6. He then exposes argument about the “Generate,” and the “product of making,” and “product of creation,” and shows the impious nature of the languag

 §7. He then clearly and skilfully criticises the doctrine of the impossibility of comparison with the things made after the Son, and exposes the idola

 §8. He proceeds to show that there is no “variance” in the essence of the Father and the Son: wherein he expounds many forms of variation and harmony,

 §9. Then, distinguishing between essence and generation, he declares the empty and frivolous language of Eunomius to be like a rattle. He proceeds to

 Book V

 Book V.

 §2. He then explains the phrase of S. Peter, “Him God made Lord and Christ.” And herein he sets forth the opposing statement of Eunomius, which he mad

 §3. A remarkable and original reply to these utterances, and a demonstration of the power of the Crucified, and of the fact that this subjection was o

 §4. He shows the falsehood of Eunomius’ calumnious charge that the great Basil had said that “man was emptied to become man,” and demonstrates that th

 §5. Thereafter he shows that there are not two Christs or two Lords, but one Christ and one Lord, and that the Divine nature, after mingling with the

 Book VI

 Book VI.

 §2. Then he again mentions S. Peter’s word, “made,” and the passage in the Epistle to the Hebrews, which says that Jesus was made by God “an Apostle a

 §3. He then gives a notable explanation of the saying of the Lord to Philip, “He that hath seen Me hath seen the Father ” and herein he excellently di

 §4. Then returning to the words of Peter, “God made Him Lord and Christ,” he skilfully explains it by many arguments, and herein shows Eunomius as an

 Book VII

 Book VII.

 §2. He then declares that the close relation between names and things is immutable, and thereafter proceeds accordingly, in the most excellent manner,

 §3. Thereafter he discusses the divergence of names and of things, speaking, of that which is ungenerate as without a cause, and of that which is non-

 §4. He says that all things that are in creation have been named by man, if, as is the case, they are called differently by every nation, as also the

 §5. After much discourse concerning the actually existent, and ungenerate and good, and upon the consubstantiality of the heavenly powers, showing the

 Book VIII

 Book VIII.

 §2. He then discusses the “willing” of the Father concerning the generation of the Son, and shows that the object of that good will is from eternity,

 §3. Then, thus passing over what relates to the essence of the Son as having been already discussed, he treats of the sense involved in “generation,”

 §4. He further shows the operations of God to be expressed by human illustrations for what hands and feet and the other parts of the body with which

 §5. Then, after showing that the Person of the Only-begotten and Maker of things has no beginning, as have the things that were made by Him, as Eunomi

 Book IX

 Book IX.

 §2. He then ingeniously shows that the generation of the Son is not according to the phrase of Eunomius, “The Father begat Him at that time when He ch

 §3. He further shows that the pretemporal generation of the Son is not the subject of influences drawn from ordinary and carnal generation, but is wit

 §4. Then, having shown that Eunomius’ calumny against the great Basil, that he called the Only-begotten “Ungenerate,” is false, and having again with

 Book X

 Book X.

 §2. He then wonderfully displays the Eternal Life, which is Christ, to those who confess Him not, and applies to them the mournful lamentation of Jere

 §3. He then shows the eternity of the Son’s generation, and the inseparable identity of His essence with Him that begat Him, and likens the folly of E

 §4. After this he shows that the Son, who truly is, and is in the bosom of the Father, is simple and uncompounded, and that, He Who redeemed us from b

 Book XI

 Book XI.

 §2. He also ingeniously shows from the passage of the Gospel which speaks of “Good Master,” from the parable of the Vineyard, from Isaiah and from Pau

 §3. He then exposes the ignorance of Eunomius, and the incoherence and absurdity of his arguments, in speaking of the Son as “the Angel of the Existen

 §4. After this, fearing to extend his reply to great length, he passes by most of his adversary’s statements as already refuted. But the remainder, fo

 §5. Eunomius again speaks of the Son as Lord and God, and Maker of all creation intelligible and sensible, having received from the Father the power a

 Book XII

 Book XII.

 §2. Then referring to the blasphemy of Eunomius, which had been refuted by the great Basil, where he banished the Only-begotten God to the realm of da

 §3. He further proceeds notably to interpret the language of the Gospel, “In the beginning was the Word,” and “Life” and “Light,” and “The Word was ma

 §4. He then again charges Eunomius with having learnt his term ἀγεννησία from the hieroglyphic writings, and from the Egyptian mythology and idolatry,

 §5. Then, again discussing the true Light and unapproachable Light of the Father and of the Son, special attributes, community and essence, and showin

§3. He then shows the eternity of the Son’s generation, and the inseparable identity of His essence with Him that begat Him, and likens the folly of Eunomius to children playing with sand.

But since, in what follows, he is active in stirring up the ill savour of his disgusting attempts, whereby he tries to make out that the Only-begotten God “once was not,” it will be well, as our mind on this head has been made pretty clear by our previous arguments, no longer to plunge our argument also in what is likewise bad, except perhaps that it is not unseasonable to add this one point, having selected it from the multitude. He says (some one having remarked that “the property of not being begotten is equally associated with the essence of the Father896    Presumably the quotation from the unknown author, if completed, would run, “as that of being begotten is associated with the essence of the Son.”    Cf. S. Matt. xix. 17.”), “The argument proceeds by like steps to those by which it came to a conclusion in the case of the Son.” The orthodox doctrine is clearly strengthened by the attack of its adversaries, the doctrine, namely, that we ought not to think that not to be begotten or to be begotten are identical with the essence897    If the property of not being begotten is “associated with” the essence, it clearly cannot be the essence, as Eunomius elsewhere maintains it to be: hence the phrase which he here adopts concedes S. Gregory’s position on this point.    i.e.as man, and not as God., but that these should be contemplated, it is true, in the subject, while the subject in its proper definition is something else beyond these, and since no difference is found in the subject, because the difference of “begotten” and “unbegotten” is apart from the essence, and does not affect it, it necessarily follows that the essence must be allowed to be in both Persons without variation. Let us moreover inquire, over and above what has been already said, into this point, in what sense he says that “generation” is alien from the Father,—whether he does so conceiving of it as an essence or an operation. If he conceives it to be an operation, it is clearly equally connected with its result and with its author, as in every kind of production one may see the operation alike in the product and the producer, appearing in the production of the effects and not separated from their artificer. But if he terms “generation” an essence separate from the essence of the Father, admitting that the Lord came into being therefrom, then he plainly puts this in the place of the Father as regards the Only-begotten, so that two Fathers are conceived in the case of the Son, one a Father in name alone, Whom he calls “the Ungenerate,” Who has nothing to do with generation, and the other, which he calls “generation,” performing the part of a Father to the Only-begotten.

And this is brought home even more by the statements of Eunomius himself than by our own arguments. For in what follows, he says:—“God, being without generation, is also prior to that which is generate,” and a little further on, “for He Whose existence arises from being generated did not exist before He was generated.” Accordingly, if the Father has nothing to do with generation, and if it is from generation that the Son derives His being, then the Father has no action in respect of the subsistence of the Son, and is apart from all connection with generation, from which the Son draws His being. If, then, the Father is alien from the generation of the Son, they either invent for the Son another Father under the name of “generation,” or in their wisdom make out the Son to be self-begotten and self-generated. You see the confusion of mind of the man who exhibits his ignorance to us up and down in his own argument, how his profanity wanders in many paths, or rather in places where no path is, without advancing to its mark by any trustworthy guidance; and as one may see in the case of infants, when in their childish sport they imitate the building of houses with sand, that what they build is not framed on any plan, or by any rules of art, to resemble the original, but first they make something at haphazard, and in silly fashion, and then take counsel what to call it,—this penetration I discern in our author. For after getting together words of impiety according to what first comes into his head, like a heap of sand, he begins to cast about to see whither his unintelligible profanity tends, growing up as it does spontaneously from what he has said, without any rational sequence. For I do not imagine that he originally proposed to invent generation as an actual subsistence standing to the essence of the Son in the place of the Father, nor that it was part of our rhetorician’s plan that the Father should be considered as alien from the generation of the Son, nor was the absurdity of self-generation deliberately introduced. But all such absurdities have been emitted by our author without reflection, so that, as regards them, the man who so blunders is not even worth much refutation, as he knows, to borrow the Apostle’s words, “neither what he says, nor whereof he affirms898    1 Tim. i. 7.    Ps. xlv. 7, 8. (The Psalm is the 44th in the LXX. numeration, and is so styled by S. Gregory.).”

“For He Whose existence arises from generation,” he says, “did not exist before generation.” If he here uses the term “generation” of the Father, I agree with Him, and there is no opponent. For one may mean the same thing by either phrase, by saying either that Abraham begat Isaac, or, that Abraham was the father of Isaac. Since then to be father is the same as to have begotten, if any one shifts the words from one form of speech to the other, paternity will be shown to be identical with generation. If, therefore, what Eunomius says is this, “He Whose existence is derived from the Father was not before the Father,” the statement is sound, and we give our vote in favour of it. But if he is recurring in the phrase to that generation of which we have spoken before, and says that it is separated from the Father but associated with the Son, then I think it waste of time to linger over the consideration of the unintelligible. For whether he thinks generation to be a self-existent object, or whether by the name he is carried in thought to that which has no actual existence, I have not to this day been able to find out from his language. For his fluid and baseless argument lends itself alike to either supposition, inclining to one side or to the other according to the fancy of the thinker.

Ἐπεὶ δὲ πολύς ἐστιν ἐν τοῖς ἐφεξῆς τῶν βδελυρῶν ἐπιχειρημάτων ἀνακινῶν τὴν δυσωδίαν, δι' ὧν μὴ εἶναί ποτε τὸν μονογενῆ κατασκευάζει θεόν, καλῶς ἔχειν φημὶ διὰ τῶν προλαβόντων μετρίως τῆς περὶ τούτων ἡμῖν διανοίας ἐκκαθαρθείσης μηκέτι συνδιαβαπτίζειν τὸν λόγον τοῖς ὁμοίοις κακοῖς. πλὴν τοῦτο μόνον οὐκ ἄκαιρον ἴσως προσθεῖναι τῶν πολλῶν ἐκλεξάμενον. φησὶ κατὰ τὸ ἴσον καὶ τῇ τοῦ πατρὸς οὐσίᾳ συνεζεῦχθαί ** τινος τὴν ἀγεννησίαν εἰπόντος διὰ τῶν ὁμοίων ὁ λόγος προέρχεται, καθὼς ἐπὶ τοῦ υἱοῦ συνεπέρανε, σαφῶς διὰ τῆς τῶν ἐναντίων κατασκευῆς τὸ δόγμα τῆς εὐσεβείας κρατύνεται, τὸ μὴ ταὐτὸν οἴεσθαι εἶναι τῇ οὐσίᾳ « τὴν ἀγεννησίαν » τε καὶ « τὴν γέννησιν », ἀλλ' ἐπιθεωρεῖσθαι μὲν ταῦτα τῷ ὑποκειμένῳ, ἄλλο δέ τι παρὰ ταῦτα εἶναι τῷ ἰδίῳ λόγῳ τὸ ὑποκείμενον, ἐφ' οὗ μηδεμιᾶς διαφορᾶς εὑρισκομένης διὰ τὸ κεχωρίσθαι τῆς οὐσίας τὴν κατὰ τὸ γεννητόν τε καὶ ἀγέννητον διαφορὰν λείπεται κατὰ πᾶσαν ἀνάγκην τὸ ἀπαράλλακτον ἐπ' ἀμφοῖν τὴν οὐσίαν συντίθεσθαι. ἔτι καὶ τοῦτο τοῖς εἰρημένοις προσεξετάσωμεν, πῶς κεχωρίσθαι τοῦ πατρὸς λέγει τὴν « γέννησιν », οὐσίαν αὐτὴν νοῶν ἢ ἐνέργειαν. ἀλλ' εἰ μὲν ἐνέργειαν οἴεται ταύτην, ἐπίσης πάντως τῷ τε ἐνεργηθέντι καὶ τῷ ἐνεργοῦντι συνάπτεται, ὥσπερ ἐπὶ πάσης κατασκευῆς ὁμοίως ἐπί τε τοῦ γινομένου καὶ τοῦ ποιοῦντος ἔστιν ἰδεῖν τὴν ἐνέργειαν μήτε τοῦ τεχνιτεύοντος χωριζομένην καὶ τῇ κατασκευῇ τῶν ἀποτελεσμάτων ἐμφαινομένην: εἰ δὲ οὐσίαν αὐτὴν λέγοι τῆς τοῦ πατρὸς οὐσίας κεχωρισμένην, ἐκ ταύτης ὁμολογῶν εἶναι τὸν κύριον, δῆλός ἐστιν ταύτην ἀντὶ τοῦ πατρὸς ἐπὶ τοῦ μονογενοῦς βλέπων, ὡς δύο πατέρας ἐπὶ τοῦ υἱοῦ νοεῖσθαι, τὸν μὲν ὀνομαζόμενον μόνον, ὃν δὴ καὶ « ἀγέννητον » λέγει, μὴ κοινωνοῦντα δὲ τῆς γεννήσεως, τὴν δὲ τὰ τοῦ πατρὸς ἐπὶ τοῦ μονογενοῦς ἐνεργοῦσαν, ἣν « γέννησιν » ὀνομάζει.
Καὶ τοῦτο μᾶλλον δι' αὐτῶν τῶν Εὐνομίου λόγων ἢ διὰ τῶν ἡμετέρων ἐλέγχεται. λέγει γὰρ ἐν τοῖς ἐφεξῆς: « ὁ δὲ θεὸς χωρὶς γεννήσεως ὢν καὶ πρὸ τοῦ γεννηθέντος ἐστί », καὶ μετ' ὀλίγον: « ᾧ γὰρ ἐκ τοῦ γεννηθῆναι τὸ εἶναι, οὗτος πρὶν γεννηθῆναι οὐκ ἦν ». οὐκοῦν εἰ ἡ γέννησις μὲν κεχώρισται τοῦ πατρός, τῷ δὲ υἱῷ ἐκ τοῦ γεννηθῆναι τὸ εἶναί ἐστιν, ἄρα ἀνενέργητος ὁ πατὴρ ἐπὶ τῆς τοῦ μονογενοῦς ὑποστάσεως καὶ κεχωρισμένος τῆς γεννήσεως, ἀφ' ἧς ὁ υἱὸς τὸ εἶναι ἔχει. εἰ οὖν ἠλλοτρίωται τῆς τοῦ υἱοῦ γεννήσεως ὁ πατήρ, ἢ ἄλλον τινὰ πατέρα τοῦ υἱοῦ διὰ τοῦ τῆς γεννήσεως ὀνόματος ἀναπλάσσουσιν ἢ αὐτογέννητόν τινα καὶ αὐτογένεθλον τὸν υἱὸν οἱ σοφοὶ διὰ τῶν εἰρημένων ἀποδεικνύουσιν. ὁρᾷς τὸ πεφυρμένον τῆς διανοίας τοῦ τὴν ἀμαθίαν ἡμῖν ἄνω καὶ κάτω διὰ τῶν ἰδίων λόγων προφέροντος, ὡς διαπλανᾶται ταῖς πολυοδίαις, μᾶλλον δὲ ταῖς ἀνοδίαις ἡ βλασφημία, δι' οὐδενὸς βεβαίου πρὸς τὸν σκοπὸν ἑαυτῆς προϊοῦσα; καὶ οἷον ἔστιν ἐπὶ τῶν νηπίων ἰδεῖν, ὅταν ὑφ' ἡλικίας ἀθύροντες ἐν ψάμμῳ τινὶ μιμῶνται τὰς τῶν οἰκοδομημάτων κατασκευάς, οἷς οὐ κατὰ σκοπὸν ἡ μίμησις τεχνικῶς πρὸς τὸ ἀρχέτυπον ὁμοιοῦται, ἀλλὰ πρότερον ὑπ' ἀνοίας τι κατὰ τὸ συμβὰν ἐξειργάσαντο, εἶτα βουλεύονται τί χρὴ ὀνομάσαι τὸ κατασκεύασμα: ταύτην καὶ ἐπὶ τοῦ λογογράφου τὴν ἀγχίνοιαν βλέπω. οἷον γάρ τινα ψάμμου σωρείαν κατὰ τὸ ἐπελθὸν αὐτῷ τὰ τῆς ἀσεβείας ῥήματα συμφορήσας μετὰ ταῦτα λογίζεται τὴν ἀδιανόητον βλασφημίαν, πρὸς ὅ τι βλέπει, δίχα τινὸς λογικῆς ἀκολουθίας ἐκ τοῦ αὐτομάτου διὰ τῶν εἰρημένων ἀναφυεῖσαν. οὐ γὰρ οἶμαι κατὰ πρόθεσιν αὐτῷ τὴν τῆς « γεννήσεως » ὑπόστασιν ἀναπεπλάσθαι ἀντὶ πατρὸς τῇ οὐσίᾳ τοῦ υἱοῦ γινομένην, οὐδὲ τὸ ἀλλότριον ἀποδειχθῆναι τῆς γεννήσεως τοῦ υἱοῦ τὸν πατέρα κατὰ σκοπὸν ἦν, ὡς οἶμαι, τῷ ῥήτορι, οὐδὲ ἡ αὐτογένεθλος τερατεία διά τινος προβουλεύσεως ἐπεισηνέχθη, ἀλλὰ πάντα τὰ τοιαῦτα διανοίας χωρὶς ἀπημέσθη τῷ λογογράφῳ, ὡς μηδὲ πολλῆς ἄξιον ἐν τούτοις κατηγορίας εἶναι τὸν πλημμελοῦντα μὲν ἐν τοῖς δόγμασιν, οὐκ εἰδότα δέ, καθώς φησιν ὁ ἀπόστολος, οὔτε ὃ λέγει οὔτε περὶ τίνων διαβεβαιοῦται. « ᾧ γὰρ ἐκ τοῦ γεννηθῆναι », φησί, « τὸ εἶναι, οὗτος πρὸ τοῦ γεννηθῆναι οὐκ ἦν ». εἰ ἀντὶ τοῦ πατρὸς νοῶν τὴν γέννησιν λέγει, κἀγὼ συντίθεμαι καὶ ὁ ἀντιλέγων οὐκ ἔστιν. ταὐτὸν γὰρ ἔστι δι' ἑκατέρας σημῆναι τῆς λέξεως ἔκ τε τοῦ εἰπεῖν ὅτι ὁ Ἀβραὰμ ἐγέννησε τὸν Ἰσαὰκ καὶ ἀντὶ τοῦ ”ἐγέννησεν” ὅτι „πατὴρ ἐγένετο„ τοῦ Ἰσαάκ. ἐπεὶ οὖν ταὐτόν ἐστι τῷ γεγεννηκέναι τὸ εἶναι πατέρα, εἴ τις πρὸς ἕτερον τύπον μεταλάβοι τὰ ῥήματα, ταὐτὸν οὖσα τῇ γεννήσει ἡ πατρότης ἀναδειχθήσεται. εἰ οὖν οὕτω φησὶν ὁ Εὐνόμιος ὅτι: ᾧ γὰρ ἐκ τοῦ πατρὸς τὸ εἶναι, οὗτος πρὸ τοῦ πατρὸς οὐκ ἦν, ὑγιαίνει ὁ λόγος, καὶ ἡμεῖς τοῖς εἰρημένοις ἐπιψηφίζομεν. εἰ δὲ πρὸς ἐκείνην ἀνατρέχει τῷ λόγῳ τὴν γέννησιν καὶ κεχωρίσθαι μέν φησι τοῦ πατρός, συνεζεῦχθαι δὲ τῷ υἱῷ, μάταιον ἡγοῦμαι τῇ τῶν ἀδιανοήτων ἐμφιλοχωρεῖν θεωρίᾳ. οὔτε γὰρ εἰ πρᾶγμα κατ' ἰδίαν ὑπόστασιν θεωρούμενον τὴν γέννησιν οἴεται οὔτε εἰ πρὸς τὸ ἀνυπόστατον ταῖς ἐννοίαις διὰ τοῦ ὀνόματος ἀποσύρεται, μέχρι τοῦ νῦν ἐκ τῶν εἰρημένων κατιδεῖν δεδυνήμεθα. φέρεται γὰρ ὁμοίως πρὸς ἑκατέραν τῶν ὑπολήψεων τὸ ἀπαγὲς τοῦ λόγου καὶ ἄρριζον, πρὸς τὸ δοκοῦν τῷ νοοῦντι περικλινόμενον.