Against Eunomius.

 Contents of Book I.

 Contents of Book II.

 Contents of Book III.

 Contents of Book IV.

 Contents of Book V.

 Contents of Book VI.

 Contents of Book VII.

 Contents of Book VIII.

 Contents of Book IX.

 Contents of Book X.

 Contents of Book XI.

 Contents of Book XII.

 §1. Preface.—It is useless to attempt to benefit those who will not accept help.

 §2. We have been justly provoked to make this Answer, being stung by Eunomius’ accusations of our brother.

 §3. We see nothing remarkable in logical force in the treatise of Eunomius, and so embark on our Answer with a just confidence.

 §4. Eunomius displays much folly and fine writing, but very little seriousness about vital points.

 §5. His peculiar caricature of the bishops, Eustathius of Armenia and Basil of Galatia, is not well drawn.

 §6. A notice of Aetius, Eunomius’ master in heresy, and of Eunomius himself, describing the origin and avocations of each.

 §7. Eunomius himself proves that the confession of faith which He made was not impeached.

 §8. Facts show that the terms of abuse which he has employed against Basil are more suitable for himself.

 §9. In charging Basil with not defending his faith at the time of the ‘Trials,’ he lays himself open to the same charge.

 §10. All his insulting epithets are shewn by facts to be false.

 §11. The sophistry which he employs to prove our acknowledgment that he had been tried, and that the confession of his faith had not been unimpeached,

 §12. His charge of cowardice is baseless: for Basil displayed the highest courage before the Emperor and his Lord-Lieutenants.

 §13. Résumé of his dogmatic teaching. Objections to it in detail.

 §14. He did wrong, when mentioning the Doctrines of Salvation, in adopting terms of his own choosing instead of the traditional terms Father, Son, and

 §15. He does wrong in making the being of the Father alone proper and supreme, implying by his omission of the Son and the Spirit that theirs is impro

 §16. Examination of the meaning of ‘subjection:’ in that he says that the nature of the Holy Spirit is subject to that of the Father and the Son. It i

 §17. Discussion as to the exact nature of the ‘energies’ which, this man declares, ‘follow’ the being of the Father and of the Son.

 §18. He has no reason for distinguishing a plurality of beings in the Trinity. He offers no demonstration that it is so.

 §19. His acknowledgment that the Divine Being is ‘single’ is only verbal.

 §20. He does wrong in assuming, to account for the existence of the Only-Begotten, an ‘energy’ that produced Christ’s Person.

 §21. The blasphemy of these heretics is worse than the Jewish unbelief.

 §22. He has no right to assert a greater and less in the Divine being. A systematic statement of the teaching of the Church.

 §23. These doctrines of our Faith witnessed to and confirmed by Scripture passages .

 §24. His elaborate account of degrees and differences in ‘works’ and ‘energies’ within the Trinity is absurd .

 §25. He who asserts that the Father is ‘prior’ to the Son with any thought of an interval must perforce allow that even the Father is not without begi

 §26. It will not do to apply this conception, as drawn out above, of the Father and Son to the Creation, as they insist on doing: but we must contempl

 §27. He falsely imagines that the same energies produce the same works, and that variation in the works indicates variation in the energies.

 §28. He falsely imagines that we can have an unalterable series of harmonious natures existing side by side.

 §29. He vainly thinks that the doubt about the energies is to be solved by the beings, and reversely.

 §30. There is no Word of God that commands such investigations: the uselessness of the philosophy which makes them is thereby proved.

 §31. The observations made by watching Providence are sufficient to give us the knowledge of sameness of Being.

 §32. His dictum that ‘the manner of the likeness must follow the manner of the generation’ is unintelligible.

 §33. He declares falsely that ‘the manner of the generation is to be known from the intrinsic worth of the generator’.

 §34. The Passage where he attacks the ‘ Ομοούσιον , and the contention in answer to it.

 §35. Proof that the Anomœan teaching tends to Manichæism.

 §36. A passing repetition of the teaching of the Church.

 §37. Defence of S. Basil’s statement, attacked by Eunomius, that the terms ‘Father’ and ‘The Ungenerate’ can have the same meaning .

 §38. Several ways of controverting his quibbling syllogisms .

 §39. Answer to the question he is always asking, “Can He who is be begotten?”

 §40. His unsuccessful attempt to be consistent with his own statements after Basil has confuted him.

 §41. The thing that follows is not the same as the thing that it follows.

 §42. Explanation of ‘Ungenerate,’ and a ‘study’ of Eternity.

 Book II

 Book II.

 §2. Gregory then makes an explanation at length touching the eternal Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit.

 §3. Gregory proceeds to discuss the relative force of the unnameable name of the Holy Trinity and the mutual relation of the Persons, and moreover the

 §4. He next skilfully confutes the partial, empty and blasphemous statement of Eunomius on the subject of the absolutely existent.

 §5. He next marvellously overthrows the unintelligible statements of Eunomius which assert that the essence of the Father is not separated or divided,

 §6. He then shows the unity of the Son with the Father and Eunomius’ lack of understanding and knowledge in the Scriptures.

 §7. Gregory further shows that the Only-Begotten being begotten not only of the Father, but also impassibly of the Virgin by the Holy Ghost, does not

 §8. He further very appositely expounds the meaning of the term “Only-Begotten,” and of the term “First born,” four times used by the Apostle.

 §9. Gregory again discusses the generation of the Only-Begotten, and other different modes of generation, material and immaterial, and nobly demonstra

 §10. He explains the phrase “The Lord created Me,” and the argument about the origination of the Son, the deceptive character of Eunomius’ reasoning,

 §11. After expounding the high estate of the Almighty, the Eternity of the Son, and the phrase “being made obedient,” he shows the folly of Eunomius i

 §12. He thus proceeds to a magnificent discourse of the interpretation of “Mediator,” “Like,” “Ungenerate,” and “generate,” and of “The likeness and s

 §13. He expounds the passage of the Gospel, “The Father judgeth no man,” and further speaks of the assumption of man with body and soul wrought by the

 §14. He proceeds to discuss the views held by Eunomius, and by the Church, touching the Holy Spirit and to show that the Father, the Son, and the Hol

 §15. Lastly he displays at length the folly of Eunomius, who at times speaks of the Holy Spirit as created, and as the fairest work of the Son, and at

 Book III

 Book III.

 §2. He then once more excellently, appropriately, and clearly examines and expounds the passage, “The Lord Created Me.”

 §3. He then shows, from the instance of Adam and Abel, and other examples, the absence of alienation of essence in the case of the “generate” and “ung

 §4. He thus shows the oneness of the Eternal Son with the Father the identity of essence and the community of nature (wherein is a natural inquiry int

 §5. He discusses the incomprehensibility of the Divine essence, and the saying to the woman of Samaria, “Ye worship ye know not what.”

 §6. Thereafter he expounds the appellation of “Son,” and of “product of generation,” and very many varieties of “sons,” of God, of men, of rams, of pe

 §7. Then he ends the book with an exposition of the Divine and Human names of the Only-Begotten, and a discussion of the terms “generate” and “ungener

 Book IV

 Book IV.

 §2. He convicts Eunomius of having used of the Only-begotten terms applicable to the existence of the earth, and thus shows that his intention is to p

 §3. He then again admirably discusses the term πρωτότοκος as it is four times employed by the Apostle.

 §4. He proceeds again to discuss the impassibility of the Lord’s generation and the folly of Eunomius, who says that the generated essence involves t

 §5. He again shows Eunomius, constrained by truth, in the character of an advocate of the orthodox doctrine, confessing as most proper and primary, no

 §6. He then exposes argument about the “Generate,” and the “product of making,” and “product of creation,” and shows the impious nature of the languag

 §7. He then clearly and skilfully criticises the doctrine of the impossibility of comparison with the things made after the Son, and exposes the idola

 §8. He proceeds to show that there is no “variance” in the essence of the Father and the Son: wherein he expounds many forms of variation and harmony,

 §9. Then, distinguishing between essence and generation, he declares the empty and frivolous language of Eunomius to be like a rattle. He proceeds to

 Book V

 Book V.

 §2. He then explains the phrase of S. Peter, “Him God made Lord and Christ.” And herein he sets forth the opposing statement of Eunomius, which he mad

 §3. A remarkable and original reply to these utterances, and a demonstration of the power of the Crucified, and of the fact that this subjection was o

 §4. He shows the falsehood of Eunomius’ calumnious charge that the great Basil had said that “man was emptied to become man,” and demonstrates that th

 §5. Thereafter he shows that there are not two Christs or two Lords, but one Christ and one Lord, and that the Divine nature, after mingling with the

 Book VI

 Book VI.

 §2. Then he again mentions S. Peter’s word, “made,” and the passage in the Epistle to the Hebrews, which says that Jesus was made by God “an Apostle a

 §3. He then gives a notable explanation of the saying of the Lord to Philip, “He that hath seen Me hath seen the Father ” and herein he excellently di

 §4. Then returning to the words of Peter, “God made Him Lord and Christ,” he skilfully explains it by many arguments, and herein shows Eunomius as an

 Book VII

 Book VII.

 §2. He then declares that the close relation between names and things is immutable, and thereafter proceeds accordingly, in the most excellent manner,

 §3. Thereafter he discusses the divergence of names and of things, speaking, of that which is ungenerate as without a cause, and of that which is non-

 §4. He says that all things that are in creation have been named by man, if, as is the case, they are called differently by every nation, as also the

 §5. After much discourse concerning the actually existent, and ungenerate and good, and upon the consubstantiality of the heavenly powers, showing the

 Book VIII

 Book VIII.

 §2. He then discusses the “willing” of the Father concerning the generation of the Son, and shows that the object of that good will is from eternity,

 §3. Then, thus passing over what relates to the essence of the Son as having been already discussed, he treats of the sense involved in “generation,”

 §4. He further shows the operations of God to be expressed by human illustrations for what hands and feet and the other parts of the body with which

 §5. Then, after showing that the Person of the Only-begotten and Maker of things has no beginning, as have the things that were made by Him, as Eunomi

 Book IX

 Book IX.

 §2. He then ingeniously shows that the generation of the Son is not according to the phrase of Eunomius, “The Father begat Him at that time when He ch

 §3. He further shows that the pretemporal generation of the Son is not the subject of influences drawn from ordinary and carnal generation, but is wit

 §4. Then, having shown that Eunomius’ calumny against the great Basil, that he called the Only-begotten “Ungenerate,” is false, and having again with

 Book X

 Book X.

 §2. He then wonderfully displays the Eternal Life, which is Christ, to those who confess Him not, and applies to them the mournful lamentation of Jere

 §3. He then shows the eternity of the Son’s generation, and the inseparable identity of His essence with Him that begat Him, and likens the folly of E

 §4. After this he shows that the Son, who truly is, and is in the bosom of the Father, is simple and uncompounded, and that, He Who redeemed us from b

 Book XI

 Book XI.

 §2. He also ingeniously shows from the passage of the Gospel which speaks of “Good Master,” from the parable of the Vineyard, from Isaiah and from Pau

 §3. He then exposes the ignorance of Eunomius, and the incoherence and absurdity of his arguments, in speaking of the Son as “the Angel of the Existen

 §4. After this, fearing to extend his reply to great length, he passes by most of his adversary’s statements as already refuted. But the remainder, fo

 §5. Eunomius again speaks of the Son as Lord and God, and Maker of all creation intelligible and sensible, having received from the Father the power a

 Book XII

 Book XII.

 §2. Then referring to the blasphemy of Eunomius, which had been refuted by the great Basil, where he banished the Only-begotten God to the realm of da

 §3. He further proceeds notably to interpret the language of the Gospel, “In the beginning was the Word,” and “Life” and “Light,” and “The Word was ma

 §4. He then again charges Eunomius with having learnt his term ἀγεννησία from the hieroglyphic writings, and from the Egyptian mythology and idolatry,

 §5. Then, again discussing the true Light and unapproachable Light of the Father and of the Son, special attributes, community and essence, and showin

§2. He then declares that the close relation between names and things is immutable, and thereafter proceeds accordingly, in the most excellent manner, with his discourse concerning “generated” and “ungenerate.”

Now seeing that the Only-begotten is in the Divine Scriptures proclaimed to be God, let Eunomius consider his own argument, and condemn for utter folly the man who parts the Divine into created and uncreated, as he does him who divides “man” into “horse” and “man.” For he himself says, a little further on, after his intermediate nonsense, “the close relation of names to things is immutable,” where he himself by this statement assents to the fixed character of the true connection of appellations with their subject. If, then, the name of Godhead is properly employed in close connection with the Only-begotten God (and Eunomius, though he may desire to be out of harmony with us, will surely concede that the Scripture does not lie, and that the name of the Godhead is not inharmoniously attributed to the Only-begotten), let him persuade himself by his own reasoning that if “the close relation of names to things is immutable,” and the Lord is called by the name of “God,” he cannot apprehend any difference in respect of the conception of Godhead between the Father and the Son, seeing that this name is common to both,—or rather not this name only, but there is a long list of names in which the Son shares, without divergence of meaning, the appellations of the Father,—“good,” “incorruptible,” “just,” “judge,” “long-suffering,” “merciful,” “eternal,” “everlasting,” all that indicate the expression of majesty of nature and power,—without any reservation being made in His case in any of the names in regard of the exalted nature of the conception. But Eunomius passes by, as it were with closed eye, the number, great as it is, of the Divine appellations, and looks only to one point, his “generate and ungenerate,”—trusting to a slight and weak cord his doctrine, tossed and driven as it is by the blasts of error.

He asserts that “no man who has any regard for the truth either calls any generated thing ‘ungenerate,’ or calls God Who is over all ‘Son’ or ‘generate.’” This statement needs no further arguments on our part for its refutation. For he does not shelter his craft with any veils, as his wont is, but treats the inversion of his absurd statement as equivalent780    That is, in making a rhetorical inversion of a proposition in itself objectionable, he so re-states it as to make it really a different proposition while treating it as equivalent. The original proposition is objectionable as classing the Son with all generated existences: the inversion of it, because the term “God” is substituted illicitly for the term “ungenerate.”, while he says that neither is any generated thing spoken of as “ungenerate,” nor is God Who is over all called “Son” or “generate,” without making any special distinction for the Only-begotten Godhead of the Son as compared with the rest of the “generated,” but makes his opposition of “all things that have come into being” to “God” without discrimination, not excepting the Son from “all things.” And in the inversion of his absurdities he clearly separates, forsooth, the Son from the Divine Nature, when he says that neither is any generated thing spoken of as “ungenerate,” nor is God called “Son” or “generate,” and manifestly reveals by this contradistinction the horrid character of his blasphemy. For when he has distinguished the “things that have come into being” from the “ungenerate,” he goes on to say, in that antistrophal induction of his, that it is impossible to call (not the “unbegotten,” but) “God,” “Son” or “generate,” trying by these words to show that which is not ungenerate is not God, and that the Only-begotten God is, by the fact of being begotten, as far removed from being God as the ungenerate is from being generated in fact or in name. For it is not in ignorance of the consequence of his argument that he makes an inversion of the terms employed thus inharmonious and incongruous: it is in his assault on the doctrine of orthodoxy that he opposes “the Godhead” to “the generate”—and this is the point he tries to establish by his words, that that which is not ungenerate is not God. What was the true sequence of his argument? that having said “no generated thing is ungenerate,” he should proceed with the inference, “nor, if anything is naturally ungenerate, can it be generate.” Such a statement at once contains truth and avoids blasphemy. But now by his premise that no generated thing is ungenerate, and his inference that God is not generated, he clearly shuts out the Only-begotten God from being God, laying down that because He is not ungenerate, neither is He God. Do we then need any further proofs to expose this monstrous blasphemy? Is not this enough by itself to serve for a record against the adversary of Christ, who by the arguments cited maintains that the Word, Who in the beginning was God, is not God? What need is there to engage further with such men as this? For we do not entangle ourselves in controversy with those who busy themselves with idols and with the blood that is shed upon their altars, not that we acquiesce in the destruction of those who are besotted about idols, but because their disease is too strong for our treatment. Thus, just as the fact itself declares idolatry, and the evil that men do boldly and arrogantly anticipates the reproach of those who accuse it, so here too I think that the advocates of orthodoxy should keep silence towards one who openly proclaims his impiety to his own discredit, just as medicine also stands powerless in the case of a cancerous complaint, because the disease is too strong for the art to deal with.

Θεοῦ τοίνυν τοῦ μονογενοῦς ἐν ταῖς θείαις κηρυσσομένου γραφαῖς, νοησάτω τὸν ἴδιον λόγον Εὐνόμιος καὶ καταγνώτω πᾶσαν ἠλιθιότητα τοῦ τὸ θεῖον τῷ κτιστῷ καὶ ἀκτίστῳ καταμερίζοντος καθ' ὁμοιότητα τοῦ τὸν ἄνθρωπον εἰς ἵππον διαιροῦντος καὶ ἄνθρωπον. λέγει γὰρ αὐτὸς μετὰ τὴν διὰ μέσου φλυαρίαν μικρὸν ὑποβὰς ὅτι « ἀμετάθετος ἡ προσφυὴς τῶν ὀνομάτων πρὸς τὰ πράγματα σχέσις ». τούτῳ καὶ αὐτὸς ἐπιψηφίζων τῷ λόγῳ τὸ πάγιον εἶναι τὴν ἀληθῆ τῶν προσηγοριῶν πρὸς τὸ ὑποκείμενον οἰκειότητα. εἰ οὖν τὸ τῆς θεότητος ὄνομα τῷ μονογενεῖ θεῷ προσφυῶς ἐπικέκληται, συνθήσεται δὲ πάντως, κἂν πρὸς ἡμᾶς ἐθέλῃ διαπληκτίζεσθαι, τὸ μὴ ψεύδεσθαι τὴν γραφὴν μηδὲ ἀπᾴδουσαν τῆς φύσεως ἐπικεῖσθαι τῷ μονογενεῖ τὴν τῆς θεότητος κλῆσιν, πεισάτω διὰ τῶν ἰδίων ἑαυτὸν ὅτι εἰ « ἀμετάθετος ἡ προσφυὴς τῶν ὀνομάτων πρὸς τὰ πράγματα σχέσις », θεὸς δὲ ὁ κύριος λέγεται, οὐ δύναται διαφοράν τινα κατὰ τὴν τῆς θεότητος ἔννοιαν ἐπὶ τοῦ υἱοῦ καὶ τοῦ πατρὸς ἐννοῆσαι, ἐπείπερ κοινὸν ἐπ' ἀμφοτέρων τοῦτο τὸ ὄνομα: μᾶλλον δὲ οὐχὶ τοῦτο μόνον, ἀλλὰ πολύς ἐστιν ὀνομάτων κατάλογος οἷς ἀπαραλλάκτως ὁ μονογενὴς τῷ πατρὶ συνονομάζεται, ἀγαθὸς ἄφθαρτος δίκαιος κριτὴς μακρόθυμος ἐλεήμων ἀΐδιος ἀτελεύτητος, πάντα ὅσα τοῦ μεγαλείου τῆς φύσεώς τε καὶ τῆς δυνάμεως τὴν σημασίαν ἐνδείκνυται, οὐδεμιᾶς ὑποστολῆς κατὰ τὸ ὑψηλὸν τῆς ἐννοίας ἔν τινι τῶν ὀνομάτων ἐπ' αὐτοῦ γινομένης. ἀλλὰ τὸν τοσοῦτον ἀριθμὸν τῶν θείων προσηγοριῶν οἷον μεμυκότι τῷ ὀφθαλμῷ παροδεύων πρὸς ἓν μόνον διαβλέπει τὸ γεννητὸν καὶ ἀγέννητον, λεπτῷ τε καὶ ἀσθενεῖ τῷ πείσματι τὸ κλυδωνιζόμενόν τε καὶ περιφερόμενον τοῖς πνεύμασι τῆς πλάνης δόγμα καταπιστεύσας. φησὶ γὰρ « μηδένα τῶν τῆς ἀληθείας πεφροντικότων οὔτε τῶν γεννητῶν οὐδὲν ὀνομάζειν ἀγέννητον οὔτε τὸν ἐπὶ πάντων θεὸν υἱὸν ἢ γεννητόν ». τοῦτο δὲ οὐκέτι τῶν ἡμετέρων ἐπιδέεται λόγων πρὸς ἔλεγχον: οὐδὲ γὰρ προκαλύμμασί τισι κατὰ τὸ σύνηθες αὐτῷ περισκέπει τὸν δόλον, ἀλλ' ἴσην ποιεῖται τοῦ ἀτόπου τὴν ἀναστροφὴν ἐν τῷ λέγειν μήτε τῶν γεννητῶν λέγεσθαί τι ἀγέννητον μήτε τὸν ἐπὶ πάντων θεὸν υἱὸν ἢ γεννητὸν ὀνομάζεσθαι, οὐδὲν κατὰ τὸ ἰδιάζον τῇ μονογενεῖ τοῦ υἱοῦ θεότητι παρὰ τὰ λοιπὰ τῶν γεννητῶν ἀποκρίνας, ἀλλ' ὁμοτίμως ποιεῖται τὴν πρὸς θεὸν διαστολὴν πάντων τῶν γεγονότων, οὐκ ἐξελὼν τὸν υἱὸν τῶν πάντων: καὶ διὰ τῆς τῶν ἀτόπων δῆθεν ἀναστροφῆς φανερῶς τὸν υἱὸν τῆς θείας ἀφίστησι φύσεως, λέγων μήτε τι τῶν γεννητῶν ἀγέννητον μήτε τὸν θεὸν υἱὸν ἢ γεννητὸν λέγεσθαι, τῇ ἀντιδιαιρέσει σαφῶς τὸ φρικτὸν ἐκκαλύπτων τῆς βλασφημίας. διαστείλας γὰρ τὰ γεγονότα πρὸς τὸ ἀγέννητον ἐν τῇ κατὰ τὸ ἀντίστροφον ἐπαγωγῇ οὐκέτι τὸν ἀγέννητον, ἀλλὰ τὸν θεὸν εἶπεν υἱὸν ἢ γεννητὸν ἀδύνατον εἶναι λέγειν, δεικνὺς διὰ τῶν εἰρημένων ὅτι τὸ μὴ ἀγέννητον θεὸς οὐκ ἔστι καὶ ὅτι τοσοῦτον ἀπέχει ὁ μονογενὴς θεὸς διὰ τὸ γεννητὸς εἶναι τοῦ εἶναι θεός, ὅσον καὶ ὁ ἀγέννητος τοῦ γεννητὸς εἶναι ἢ λέγεσθαι. οὐ γὰρ ἀγνοίᾳ τῆς κατὰ τὸν λόγον ἀκολουθίας ἀσύμφωνόν τε καὶ ἀνάρμοστον ποιεῖται τῶν τεθέντων τὴν ἀναστροφήν, ἀλλὰ κακουργῶν τῆς εὐσεβείας τὸν λόγον ἀντιδιαστέλλει τῷ γεννητῷ τὴν θεότητα, τοῦτο δι' ὧν λέγει κατασκευάζων, ὅτι τὸ μὴ ἀγέννητον θεὸς οὐκ ἔστιν. ἡ γὰρ ἀληθὴς ἀκολουθία τοῦ λόγου τίς ἦν; εἰπόντα μηδὲν τῶν γεννητῶν εἶναι ἀγέννητον, ἐπαγαγεῖν ὅτι οὐδὲ εἴ τι κατὰ φύσιν ἐστὶν ἀγέννητον, γεννητὸν εἶναι δύναται. ὁ γὰρ τοιοῦτος λόγος καὶ τὸ ἀληθὲς ἔχει καὶ τῆς βλασφημίας κεχώρισται. νῦν δὲ τῷ προθεῖναι μὲν ὅτι τῶν γεννητῶν οὐδέν ἐστιν ἀγέννητον, ἐπαγαγεῖν δὲ ὅτι οὐδὲ γεννητὸς ὁ θεός, σαφῶς τοῦ εἶναι θεὸν τὸν μονογενῆ θεὸν ἀφορίζει, διὰ τοῦ μὴ ἀγέννητον αὐτὸν εἶναι τὸ μηδὲ θεὸν αὐτὸν εἶναι κατασκευάζων. ἆρ' οὖν ἑτέρων ἔτι πρὸς ἀπόδειξιν τῆς ἐκτόπου ταύτης βλασφημίας τῶν ἐλέγχων δεόμεθα καὶ οὐκ ἀρκεῖ τοῦτο μόνον ἀντὶ στήλης γενέσθαι τῷ χριστομάχῳ τῷ κατασκευάζοντι διὰ τῶν εἰρημένων μὴ εἶναι θεὸν τὸν ἐν ἀρχῇ ὄντα λόγον θεόν; τί οὖν ἔτι χρὴ πρὸς τοὺς τοιούτους συμπλέκεσθαι; οὐδὲ γὰρ τοῖς περὶ τὰ εἴδωλα καὶ τὸν ἐπιβώμιον λύθρον ἀσχολουμένοις διαπλεκόμεθα, οὐχὶ τῷ συντίθεσθαι τῇ ἀπωλείᾳ τῶν εἰδωλομανούντων, ἀλλὰ τῷ βαρυτέραν εἶναι τὴν νόσον αὐτῶν τῆς παρ' ἡμῶν θεραπείας. ὥσπερ τοίνυν τὴν εἰδωλολατρείαν αὐτὸ καταμηνύει τὸ ἔργον καὶ προλαμβάνει τῶν κατηγόρων τὸν ἔλεγχον τὸ κακὸν ἐν παρρησίᾳ τολμώμενον, οὕτω καὶ ἐνταῦθα σιγᾶν οἶμαι δεῖν τὸν τῆς εὐσεβείας συνήγορον πρὸς τὸν βοῶντα καθ' ἑαυτοῦ περιφανῶς τὴν ἀσέβειαν, καθάπερ καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν τῷ καρκινώδει πάθει κεκρατημένων ἄπρακτος ἡ ἰατρικὴ μένει διὰ τὸ ὑπερισχύειν τῆς τέχνης τὴν νόσον.