Gabala

 Gabbatha

 Vicariate Apostolic of Gaboon

 Gabriel

 Brothers of Saint Gabriel

 Bl. Gabriel Possenti

 Gabriel Sionita

 Gad

 Gadara

 Agnolo, Giovanni, and Taddeo Gaddi

 Archdiocese of Gaeta

 Ivan Sergejewitch Gagarin

 Achille Gagliardi

 William Gahan

 Claude Ferdinand Gaillard

 St. Gal

 Epistle to the Galatians

 Pietro Colonna Galatino

 Valerius Maximianus Galerius

 Joseph Galien

 Galilee

 Alessandro Galilei

 Galileo Galilei

 Elizabeth Galitzin

 St. Gall

 Abbey of St. Gall

 St. Galla

 Vicariate Apostolic of Galla

 Louis Gallait

 Antoine Galland

 Andrea Gallandi

 Diocese of Galle

 Juan Nicasio Gallego

 Pietro Luigi Galletti

 Gallia Christiana

 Gallicanism

 Gallican Rite

 Sts. Gallicanus

 Publius Licinius Egnatius Gallienus

 Joseph de Gallifet

 Diocese of Gallipoli

 Adele Amalie Gallitzin

 Demetrius Augustine Gallitzin

 Diocese of Galloway

 Pasquale Galluppi

 Peter Gallwey

 Diocese of Galtelli-Nuoro

 Bernhard Galura

 Luigi Galvani

 Diocese of Galveston

 Diocese of Galway and Kilmacduagh

 Vasco da Gama

 Gamaliel

 Jean Gamans

 Gambling

 Pius Bonifacius Gams

 Peter Gandolphy

 Gangra

 Diocese of Gap

 Anne García

 St. Gonsalo Garcia

 Gabriel García Moreno

 Garcilasso de la Vega

 Garcilasso de la Vega (the Inca)

 Aloisio Gardellini

 Stephen Gardiner

 Julius Peter Garesché

 Jean Garet

 Gargara

 André Garin

 Garland

 John Garland

 Ven. Nicholas Garlick

 François-Xavier Garneau

 Henry Garnet

 Ven. Thomas Garnet

 Charles Garnier

 Jean Garnier

 Julien Garnier

 Raffaele Garrucci

 Diocese of Garzon

 Bl. Gaspare del Bufalo

 Philippe-Aubert de Gaspe

 Pierre Gassendi

 Joseph Gasser von Valhorn

 Johann Joseph Gassner

 William Gaston

 St. Gatianus

 Franz Christian Gau

 Antoine Gaubil

 St. Gaudentius

 Gaudentius of Brescia

 Gaudete Sunday

 Antoine le Gaudier

 Gaudiosus

 Christian Gaul

 Giovanni Battista Gaulli

 Aloisius-Edouard-Camille Gaultier

 Jean-Joseph Gaume

 Bartolommeo Gavantus

 Charles Etienne Arthur Gayarré

 Gaza

 Pietro Maria Gazzaniga

 Gebhard (III) of Constance

 Emile Gebhart

 Gedeon

 Nicolas Gédoyn

 Josef Anton von Gegenbauer

 Johann Geiler von Kaysersberg

 Johannes von Geissel

 Pope St. Gelasius I

 Pope Gelasius II

 Gelasius of Cyzicus

 Gemblours

 Genealogy (in the Bible)

 Genealogy of Christ

 Gilbert Génebrard

 General Chapter

 Generation

 Genesareth

 Genesis

 Genesius

 St. Genevieve

 Land of Genezareth

 Girolamo Genga

 Edward Génicot

 St. Gennadius I

 Gennadius II

 Gennadius of Marseilles

 Edmund and John Gennings

 Archdiocese of Genoa

 Gentile da Fabriano

 Gentiles

 Aloysius Gentili

 Genuflexion

 Geoffrey of Clairvaux

 Geoffrey of Dunstable

 Geoffrey of Monmouth

 Geoffrey of Vendôme

 Biblical Geography

 Geography and the Church

 St. George

 George Hamartolus

 George of Trebizond

 George Pisides

 George the Bearded

 Georgetown University

 Georgia

 Georgius Syncellus

 Diocese of Gerace

 St. Gerald

 Diocese of Geraldton

 Baron Ferdinand de Géramb

 Joseph-Marie de Gérando

 St. Gérard, Abbot of Brogne

 St. Gerard, Bishop of Toul

 Gerard, Archbishop of York

 John Gerard

 Ven. Miles Gerard

 Richard Gerard

 St. Gerard Majella

 Gerard of Cremona

 Gerardus Odonis

 Gerasa

 Gabriel Gerberon

 Martin Gerbert

 Olympe-Philippe Gerbet

 Jean-François Gerbillon

 Hyacinthe Sigismond Gerdil

 Gerhard of Zütphen

 Gerhoh of Reichersberg

 St. Germain (1)

 St. Germain (2)

 St. Germaine Cousin

 Bl. German Gardiner

 Germanicia

 Germanicopolis

 Germans in the United States

 St. Germanus I

 Germany

 Vicariate Apostolic of Northern Germany

 Germia

 Diocese of Gerona

 Gerrha

 Jean le Charlier de Gerson

 Bl. Gertrude of Aldenberg

 Gertrude of Hackeborn

 St. Gertrude of Nivelles

 St. Gertrude the Great

 Ven. Gertrude van der Oosten

 Dom François Armand Gervaise

 George Gervase

 Gervase of Canterbury

 Gervase of Tilbury

 Sts. Gervasius and Protasius

 St. Géry

 Gesellenvereine

 Gesta Dei per Francos

 Gesta Romanorum

 Gethsemani

 Abbey of Our Lady of Gethsemani

 Gezireh

 August Friedrich Gfrörer

 Prefecture Apostolic of Ghardaia

 Diocese of Ghent

 Lorenzo di Cione Ghiberti

 Ghirlandajo

 St. Ghislain

 Ghost Dance

 Pietro Giannone

 Gibail and Batrun

 Pierre Gibault

 John Gibbons

 Richard Gibbons

 Jean-Pierre Gibert

 Gian Matteo Giberti

 Vicariate Apostolic of Gibraltar

 Bonaventure Giffard

 Godfrey Giffard

 William Giffard

 William Gifford

 Supernatural Gift

 Nicolas-Joseph-Laurent Gilbert

 Sir John Thomas Gilbert

 Gilbert de la Porrée

 Gilbert Foliot

 Order of Gilbertines

 Vicariate Apostolic of the Gilbert Islands

 St. Gilbert of Sempringham

 St. Gildas

 Alvarez Carillo Gil de Albornoz

 St. Giles

 Gillespie

 James Gillis

 Patrick Sarsfield Gilmore

 Bl. Gil of Santarem

 Gindarus

 Jacques-Marie-Achille Ginoulhiac

 Vincenzo Gioberti

 Fra Giovanni Giocondo

 Tommaso Giordani

 Luca Giordano

 Giorgione

 Giotto di Bondone

 Ruggiero Giovanelli

 Giovanni Battista Giraldi

 Ubaldo Giraldi

 Giraldus Cambrensis

 Jean-Baptiste Girard

 François Girardon

 Giraud de Borneil

 Girba

 Girgenti

 Blaise Gisbert

 Giulio Romano

 Bl. Giuseppe Maria Tommasi

 Giuseppe Giusti

 Raoul Glaber

 Manius Acilius Glabrio

 Glagolitic

 Jean-Baptiste Glaire

 Ranulf de Glanville

 Henry Glarean

 Archdiocese of Glasgow

 Glastonbury Abbey

 Glebe

 School of Glendalough

 Gloria in Excelsis Deo

 Glory

 Scriptural Glosses

 Glosses, Glossaries, Glossarists

 Episcopal Gloves

 Gluttony

 Archdiocese of Gnesen-Posen

 Gnosticism

 Archdiocese of Goa

 Vicariate Apostolic of Goajira

 St. Goar

 Jacques Goar

 George Gobat

 Gobban Saer

 Person Gobelinus

 God

 St. Godard

 Thomas Godden

 Antoine Godeau

 St. Godeberta

 St. Godelina

 Paul Godet des Marais

 Godfrey of Bouillon

 Godfrey of Fontaines

 Godfrey of Viterbo

 Godric

 Marie Josephine Goetz

 Stephen Goffe

 Leonard Goffine

 Gog and Magog

 Golden Calf

 Golden Rose

 Carlo Goldoni

 Thomas Goldwell

 Francisco Lopez de Gómara

 Francisco Gomes De Amorim

 Gondulphus

 Jean Baptiste Gonet

 Jérôme de Gonnelieu

 Ercole Gonzaga

 Scipione Gonzaga

 Thyrsus González de Santalla

 Gonzalo de Berceo

 Good

 Highest Good

 Good Faith

 Good Friday

 Eastern Vicariate of the Cape of Good Hope

 Western Vicariate of the Cape of Good Hope

 Godfrey Goodman

 Ven. John Goodman

 Sisters of the Good Samaritan

 Our Lady of Charity of the Good Shepherd

 Pierre-Lambert Goossens

 Gordian

 Sts. Gordianus and Epimachus

 Andrew Gordon

 Gordon Riots

 Gordos

 St. Gorgonius

 Martyrs of Gorkum

 Guido Görres

 Johann Joseph Görres

 Gortyna

 Görz

 Goscelin

 Gospel and Gospels

 Gospel in the Liturgy

 Alexander Goss

 Jan Gossaert

 Jean-Edmé-Auguste Gosselin

 John Gother

 Gothic Architecture

 Gottfried von Strasburg

 St. Gottschalk

 Gottschalk of Orbais

 Abbey of Göttweig

 Diocese of Goulburn

 Charles-François Gounod

 René Goupil

 Thomas-Marie-Joseph Gousset

 John Gower

 Francisco José de Goya y Lucientes

 Diocese of Goyaz

 Diocese of Gozo

 Carlo Gozzi

 Gozzoli

 Grace

 Controversies on Grace

 William Russell Grace

 Grace at Meals

 Gradual

 Gradual Psalms

 Robert Gradwell

 Graffiti

 Patrick Graham

 Holy Grail

 Eugénie de Gramont

 Archdiocese of Gran

 Archdiocese of Granada

 University of Granada

 Jean Grancolas

 Theodor Granderath

 Philippe-André Grandidier

 Abbey and Order of Grandmont

 Diocese of Grand Rapids

 Thomas Grant

 Antoine Perrenot de Granvelle

 François-Joseph-Paul Grasse

 Lorenz Grässel

 Paris de Grassis

 Gratian

 Jerome Gratian

 Johannes Gratian

 Gratianopolis

 Ortwin Gratius

 Auguste-Joseph-Alphonse Gratry

 Peter Aloys Gratz

 Jacques Gravier

 Dominic Gravina

 Giovanni Vincenzo Gravina

 Diocese of Gravina and Montepeloso

 University of Graz

 Great Falls

 Greece

 Greek Catholics in America

 Greek Church

 Greek Orthodox Church in America

 Greek Rites

 Hugh Green

 Thomas Louis Green

 Diocese of Green Bay

 Greenland

 Gregorian Chant

 Pope St. Gregory I

 Pope St. Gregory II

 Pope St. Gregory III

 Pope Gregory IV

 Pope Gregory V

 Pope Gregory VI

 Gregory VI (Antipope)

 Pope St. Gregory VII

 Pope Gregory VIII

 Gregory VIII

 Pope Gregory IX

 Pope Gregory X

 Pope Gregory XI

 Volume 8

 Pope Gregory XII

 Pope Gregory XIII

 Pope Gregory XIV

 Pope Gregory XV

 Pope Gregory XVI

 Gregory Bæticus

 Gregory of Heimburg

 St. Gregory of Nazianzus

 St. Gregory of Neocaesarea

 St. Gregory of Nyssa

 Gregory of Rimini

 St. Gregory of Tours

 St. Gregory of Utrecht

 Gregory of Valencia

 Gregory the Illuminator

 University of Greifswald

 Karl Johann Greith

 Gremiale

 Diocese of Grenoble

 Dietrich Gresemund

 Adrien Greslon

 Jean Baptiste Gresset

 Jacob Gretser

 Jean-Baptiste Greuze

 Grey Nuns

 Grey Nuns of the Cross

 Gerald Griffin

 Thomas Griffiths

 Franz Grillparzer

 Francesco Maria Grimaldi

 Giovanni Francesco Grimaldi

 Johann Jacob Christoffel von Grimmelshausen

 Valentin Gröne

 Gerard Groote

 John Gropper

 Robert Grosseteste

 Diocese of Grosseto

 Diocese of Grosswardein

 Abbey of Grottaferrata

 Johann Grueber

 Anastasius Grün

 Archdiocese of Guadalajara (Guadalaxara)

 Shrine of Guadalupe

 Diocese of Guadeloupe

 Guaicuri Indians

 Guaraní Indians

 Law of Guarantees

 Diocese of Guarda

 Francesco Guardi

 Guardian Angel

 Feast of Guardian Angels

 Guardianship

 Battista Guarini

 Guarino da Verona

 Diocese of Guastalla

 Guastallines

 Archdiocese of Santiago de Guatemala

 Diocese of Guayaquil

 Diocese of Gubbio

 Moritz Gudenus

 St. Gudula

 Guelphs and Ghibellines

 Prosper Louis Pascal Guéranger

 Robert Guérard

 Anne-Thérèse Guérin

 Guérin

 Joseph Heinrich Aloysius Gügler

 Giovanni Battista Guglielmini

 Guiana

 Guibert of Ravenna

 Francesco Guicciardini

 Guido of Arezzo

 Guigues du Chastel

 André Guijon

 Guilds

 Patrick Robert Guiney

 Robert Guiscard

 House of Guise

 Guitmund

 Vicariate Apostolic of Gulf of St. Lawrence

 Gunpowder Plot

 Bl. Gunther

 Anton Günther

 Günther of Cologne

 Diocese of Gurk

 Jean-Pierre Gury

 Bartholomeu Lourenço de Gusmão

 Johann Gutenberg

 St. Guthlac

 Jeanne-Marie Bouvier de La Motte-Guyon

 Fernando Pérez de Guzmán

 Diocese of Györ

Highest Good


"We always act with a view to some good. The good is the object which all pursue, and for the sake of which they always act", says Plato (Republic, I, vi). His disciple Aristotle repeats the same idea in other words when he declares (Ethics, I, i) that the good is "that which all aim at". This definition is, as St. Thomas observes, a posteriori. Yet, if appetibility does not constitute goodness, still it is our only means of identifying it; in practice, the good is the desirable. But experience soon teaches that all desires cannot be satisfied, that they are conflicting, and that some goods must be foregone in order to secure others. Hence the necessity of weighing the relative value of goods, of classifying them, and of ascertaining which of them must be procured even at the loss of others. The result is the division of goods into two great classes, the physical and the moral, happiness and virtue. Within either class it is comparatively easy to determine the relation of particular good things to one another, but it has proved far more difficult to fix the relative excellence of the two classes of virtue and happiness. Still the question is of supreme importance, since in it the reason and final destiny of our life is involved. As Cicero says (De Finibus, v, 6), "Summum autem bonum si ignoratur, vivendi rationem ignorari necesse est." If happiness and virtue are mutually exclusive, we have to choose between the two, and this choice is a momentous one. But their incompatibility may be only on the surface. Indeed the hope is ever recurring that the sovereign good includes both, and that there is some way of reconciling them.

It has been the task of moralists to sift the conditions on which this may be done.


  • Some would reduce virtue to happiness;
  • others teach that happiness is to be found in virtue;
  • but, as both these solutions are ever found to be in contradiction with the facts of life, the consequent vacillations of opinion can be traced throughout the history of philosophy.

In the main, they can be classified under three heads, according as one or the other predominates, or both are made to blend: viz.:


  • Eudæmonism or Utilitarianism, when the highest good is identified with happiness;
  • Rational Deontologism, when the highest good is identified with virtue or duty;
  • Rational Eudæmonism, or tempered Deontologism, when both virtue and happiness are combined in the highest good.


I. EUDÆMONISM

(a) Socrates (469-399 B. C.), the father of systematic Ethics, taught that happiness is the end of man; that it consists, not in external goods signs of the uncertain favours of fortune, or of the gods (eutychia) — but in a rational joy, which implies the renunciation of common delights (eupraxia). He did not, however, carry this doctrine of moderation to the degree of asceticism, but rather insisted on the cultivation of the mind as being of greater importance. Knowledge is the only virtue, ignorance the only vice. Yet, from the Dialogues of Xenophon, it is seen that he descends to the common morality of Utilitarianism.

(b) This latter phase of Socratic teaching was adopted by Aristippus of Cyrene (435-356 B. C.), who as representative of the Hedonistic School among the ancients, and holding, on the one hand, with Socrates that knowledge is virtue, and, on the other, with Protagoras, that we can know only our sensations, and not that which causes them, concluded that that which produces in us the most pleasant feelings is the highest good. Culture and virtue are desirable only as a means to this end. As pleasure is conditioned by organic states, it can be produced only by motion, which, to be pleasant, must needs be gentle; hence according to the Cyrenaics, it is not the mere absence of pain, but a transient emotion which makes man happy and constitutes his highest good.

(c) Aristotle (384-322 B. C.) admits with Socrates and the ancient philosophers generally, that the highest good is to be identified with the highest happiness; and, in determining in what this highest happiness consists, he agrees with the Cyrenaics that it is not mere passing enjoyment, but action (en to zen kai energein, Eth, Nic., IX, ix, 5). Still it is not any and every kind of activity that man may find agreeable which constitutes this supreme happiness, but that which is proper to him (okeion ergon — oikeia arete, Ibid., I, vii, 15). This cannot be merely the life which he shares with the plants and animals, or the sensibility, which he enjoys in common with the brutes, but thought, which is the distinctive characteristic of man. Moreover, as it is in the sphere of activity proper to each living being that its peculiar excellence is to be sought, it follows that man's rational activity (psyches energeia meta logou, Ibid., I, vii, 15) is at the same time honourable and virtuous (psyches energeia kat areten, loc. cit.). Since, however, there are several such activities, it must be the noblest and most perfect of these. This is none other than speculative thought, or that which has to do with the contemplation of "honourable and divine subjects" (kalon kai theion, Ibid., X, vii, 10), because this belongs to the noblest faculty and tends to the noblest object; because it is the most continuous, the most pleasant, the most self-sufficing (Ibid., I, x, 8).

In thus defining human happiness, Aristotle does not aim at determining which good is absolutely supreme, but only that which relatively is the highest for man in his present condition — the highest attainable in this life (to panton akrotaton ton prakton agathon, Ibid., I, iv, 16). Though Aristotle thus makes happiness and the highest good to consist in virtuous action, yet he does not exclude pleasure, but holds that pleasure in its keenest form springs from virtue. Pleasure completes an action, is added to it, as "to youth its bloom" (oion tois akmaiois he ora, Ibid., X, iv, 8). Since, therefore, Aristotle places man's highest good in his perfection, which is identical with his happiness and carries with it pleasure, he is rightly accounted a Eudæmonist, though of a nobler sort.

(d) Epicurus (circa 340-270 B. C.), whilst accepting in substance the Hedonism of the Cyrenaics, does not admit with them that the highest good lies in the pleasure of motion (hedone en kinesei), but rather in the pleasure of rest (hedone kataskematike); not in the voluptas in motu but in the stabilitas voluptatis, says Cicero (De Finibus, II, v, 3) — that state of deep peace and perfect contentment in which we feel secure against all the storms of life (ataraxia). To attain this is the paramount problem of Epicurus's philosophy, to which his empirical logic (canonics) and his theory of nature (the materialism of Democritus) are merely preliminaries. Thus the whole of his philosophy is constructed with a view to his Ethics, for which it prepares the way and which completes it.

In holding that the pleasures of the mind are preferable to voluptuousness, inasmuch as they endure, while those of the senses pass with the moment that gives them birth, he is not consistent, seeing that his materialism reduces all the operations of the mind to mere sensations. Finally, as virtue is according to him the tact which impels the wise man to do whatever contributes to his welfare, and makes him avoid the contrary, it cannot be the highest good, but only a means of realizing it. By his materialism Epicurus paved the way for modern Utilitarianism, which has assumed two forms, viz.:

(e) Individual Utilitarianism, which places man's highest good in his greatest personal welfare and pleasure. This is identical with the Greek Hedonism, and was revived in the eighteenth century by the Encyclopedists, De la Mettrie (1709-1751), Helvetius (1715-1771), Diderot (1713-1784), and De Volney (1757-1820). It was also advocated by the Sensists, Hartley (1704-1757), Priestley (1733-1804) and Hume (1711-1776); and in the nineteenth century by the German Materialists, Vogt (1817-1895), Moleschott (1822-1893), and Büchner (1824-1899);

(f) Social Utilitarianism, which is mainly of English origin. In its earliest stage, with Richard Cumberland (1632-1718), and Anthony Cooper, Earl of Shaftesbury (1671-1718), it still retained a somewhat subjective character, and placed the highest good in the practice of social benevolence. With Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806-1873), it becomes wholly objective. The highest good, so they say, cannot be the happiness of the individuai, but the happiness of the many, "the greatest happiness of the greatest number". Stated in these terms, the proposition is merely a truism. That in general, the happiness of a community is superior to the happiness of one of its members, is obvious; but, when it comes to be a personal affair, the individuai is no longer a part of the whole, but one party pitted against others, and it is by no means evident, from the positivistic point of view, that his personal happiness is not for him the highest good.

(g) This passage from self to non-self, from the individual to the community, Herbert Spencer (1820-1903) attempted to derive from the evolutionary principle of "the survival of the fittest". Those individuals have evidently a better chance to survive who oppose their enemies as a body, and therefore who live in societies (flocks, herds, human associations); and therefore, again, the social instincts are destined to survive and grow stronger, while the individualistic ones cannot but disappear. The highest good here is not the happiness of the individual, not even the happiness of the present generation, but the sum total of the conditions which make possible the survival and the constant progress of mankind at large. Hence in a system of elaborate synthetic philosophy Spencer discusses at great length the laws of life and those conditions of psychologie and social existence from which, as from a prearranged premise, he gathers "The Data of Ethics", or Ethics emancipated from the notion of divine legislation.


II. DEONTOLOGISM

Under this head may be classed systems which place the highest human good in the conformity of conduct with reason. It assumes an exaggerated or tempered form, according as it excludes or admits regard for human perfection and happiness as one of the elements of morality.

(a) Plato, in common with Socrates and the minor Socratic schools, holds that happiness is the supreme and ultimate object of human endeavour, and that this happiness is identical with the highest good. But when he comes to determine in what this good or happiness consists, he does so in accordance with the presuppositions of his philosophical system. The soul in its true essence is declared to be an incorporeal spirit destined for the intuition of the Idea; hence its ultimate end and supreme good is to be attained by withdrawing from the life of sense and retiring into pure contemplation of the Idea, which is identical with God. Man must, therefore, rise to God and find his chief good in Him. This may be considered the highest good in the objective order, and is found inculcated in those passages of this philosopher's writings in which the solution of the supreme problem of life is sought in flight from sensuality (cf. Theæt., 176, A; Phædo, 64, E; Republic, VII, 519, C sqq., apud Zeller, pp. 435-444). But inasmuch as this is practically unattainable in this life, man is told that the highest good here is to be found in making himself like God, and that this is to be brought about by the knowledge and the enthusiastic love of God, as the Supreme Good. In the knowledge, therefore, and love of God as the Supreme Good consists man's highest good in the subjective order. This is brought out in those passages in which even sensuous beauty is described as worthy of love, and external activity, sensible pleasure, is included among the component elements of the highest good (cf. Republic, X, 603, E sqq.; Phil.,28,A sqq.; Tim., 59, C).

(b) The Stoic school was founded by Zeno of Cittium (350-258 B. C.). According to its followers, the highest purpose (good) of human life is not to be found in contemplation (theoria), as Plato would have it, but in action. To live according to nature (homologoumenos te physei zen) was their supreme rule of conduct. By this they did not mean that individual nature of man, but the eternal and divine law which manifests itself in nature as the measure to which all things in the universe should conform their action. For man to live according to nature, therefore, means to conform his will to the divine will, and in this consists virtue. Virtue alone is good in the highest sense of the word, and virtue alone is sufficient for happiness. As this law imposes itself through reason, the system is rightly called rational Deontologism.

(c) Kant agrees with the Stoics in placing the essence of the highest good in virtue, and not in happiness. Yet he thinks our conception of it is incomplete unless it is made to include happiness as well. The highest good may mean either the Supreme (supremum) or the Complete (consummatum). The Supreme is a condition which is itself unconditioned, or is not subordinate to anything else (originarium). The Complete, again, is a whole which is not itself a part of a larger whole of the same kind (perfectissimum). Virtue, or that disposition to act in conformity with the moral law, is not dependent on happiness, but itself makes man worthy of happiness. It is, therefore, the highest good, the supreme condition of whatever can be regarded as desirable. But it is not the whole, nor the supreme good, which finite rational beings crave; the complete good includes happiness. Hence the highest conceivable good must consist in the union of virtue and happiness proportioned to morality.

This is what Kant means by the whole or complete good. Of its two elements, virtue, having no higher condition and being itself the condition of happiness, is the supreme good. Happiness, however, while it is agreeable to the person who possesses it, is not good in itself and in all respects; it is good only under the condition that a man's conduct is in conformity with the moral law. This is why Kant was wont to say that "nothing can be called good without qualification, but good will"; and since the best it can do in this life is to strive after holiness, the struggle between the desire to obey and the impulse to transgress must continue for ever, making the highest good in this life unattainable.


III. RATIONAL EUDÆMONISM OR TEMPERED DEONTOLOGISM

Christian philosophers, in dealing with the problem of the highest good, have necessarily kept in view the teachings of Faith; still they base their solution of it on motives of reason. Their system is neither strictly deontologico-rational, nor yet altogether eudemonistic, but a consistent blending of both. The ultimate end of man is to be placed in perfect rational activity, in ultimate perfection, and in happiness, not as in three different things, but as in one and the self-same, since the three conceptions are resolvable into one another, and each of them denotes a goal of human tendency, a limit beyond which no desire remains to be satisfied. Though they differ somewhat in their several ways of formulating it, at bottom they all agree:


  • that in the blissful possession of God is to be found the rightful object of reason (man's deontologico-rational end), and of free will (his eudæmonistic end);
  • that this eudæmonistic end — the perfect satisfaction of the will in the possession of God — is not merely an accidental result of the former, but is the positive determination of God, the author of our nature;
  • that this eudæmonistic end may not be intended by the will for its own sake, to the exclusion of the deontologico-rational end, which, by its nature, it presupposes, and to which it is subordinated.

It is St. Thomas Aquinas who best harmonized this system with revelation. His teaching may be summarized thus:

(a) Man's highest happiness does not consist in pleasure, but in action, since, in the nature of things, action is not for pleasure, but pleasure for action. This activity, on which man's happiness rests, must, on the one hand, be the noblest and highest of which his nature is capable, and, on the other, it must be directed toward the noblest and the highest object.

(b) This noblest and highest object of human activity is not that of the will, which merely follows upon and is conditioned by knowledge; it must rather be knowledge itself. Consequently, the highest happiness of man consists in the knowledge of the highest truth, which is God, With the knowledge of God must, of course, be joined the love of God; but this love is not the essential element of perfect happiness; it is merely a necessary complement of it (Summa Theol., I-II, Q. iii, a. 2, c; Con. Gen., III, xxv, xxvi).

(c) Since the knowledge of God can be acquired in three ways — by demonstration, by faith, and by intuition — the further question arises: which of these three kinds of knowledge is the foundation of man's highest happiness? Not knowledge by demonstration, for happiness must be something universal and attainable by all men, whereas only a few can arrive at this knowledge by demonstration; neither can knowledge by faith be a basis for perfect happiness, seeing that this consists chiefly in the activity of the intellect, whilst in faith the will claims for itself the principal part, inasmuch as the will must here determine the intellect to give its assent. Consequently happiness can consist only in the intuitive knowledge of God; and since this is attainable only in the next life, it follows that the ultimate destiny of man — and hence his highest good — reaches beyond time into eternity. It must be everlasting, otherwise it would not be perfect (Con. Gent., III, xxxviii, sqq.).

(d) This end is not merely a subjective one which the reason imposes upon itself. Just because it is an activity, it involves relation to some external object. The intellect essentially represents a truth distinct from itself, as the act of the will is an inclination towards some good not identical with itself, The truth to be represented, therefore, and the good to be attained or possessed, are objects to which happiness refers as to further ends, just as the image has reference to a model and motion to a goal. Truth, therefore, and good are objective ends to which formal happiness corresponds as a subjective end. The absolutely ultimate end, therefore, is in the objective order, beyond which nothing remains to be known and desired, and which, when it is known and possessed, gives rest to the rational faculties. This can be nothing else than the infinite truth and the infinite good, which is God, Hence the system is not a purely deontologico-rational one, constituting the reason a law to itself, the observance of which law would be the highest good.

(e) Still less is it purely eudæmonistic, since the ultimate end and highest gond does not coincide with subjective happiness as Hedonism teaches, but with the object of the highest acts of contemplation and love. This object is God, not merely as beatifying us, but as the Absolute Truth and Goodness, infinitely perfect in itself.

UEBERWEG, History of Philosophy (New York, 1872); TURNER, History of Philosophy (Boston, 1903); STOECKL-FINLAY, History of Philosophy (Dublin, 1903); KANT, Critique of Practical Reason, ed. ABBOTT (London, 1898); ZELLER, Aristotle and the Earlier Peripatetics, II (London, 1897); IDEM, Plato and the Older Academy (London, 1888); JANET AND SÉAILLES, History of the Problem of Philosophy, II (London, 1902), BYWATER, Aristotelis Ethica Nicomachea (Oxford, 1894); MING, Data of Modern Ethics Examined (New York, 1894); MEYER, Institutiones Juris Naturalis, I (Freiburg im Br., 1885); S. Thomœ Aquinatis Summa Theologica; Summa contra Gentiles; SUAREZ, De Ultimo Fine Hominis.

M. F. Dinneen.